[PDF] CONCEPTUAL DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS PART II: CUBIC





Previous PDF Next PDF



Calculus II Lecture Notes

Calculus II. Integral Calculus. Lecture Notes. Veselin Jungic & Jamie Mulholland. Department of Mathematics. Simon Fraser University c Draft date January 2 



Calculus II - Examen

Calculus II. Examen. (1er septembre 2021). Nom : Prénom : Section : Lisez ces quelques consignes avant de commencer l'examen.



Calculus II for Dummies

Calculus II is harder even



Jerrold Marsden and Alan Weinstein

FlaniganIKazdan: Calculus Two: Linear and Nonlinear Functions. Second edition. This book is an outgrowth of our teaching of calculus at Berkeley and.



calculus-cm1.pdf

Calculus ?. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10. 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20. Page 2. Calculus ?. 1. Calcule : +. Calculus ?. 2. Calcule : +. Calculus ?.



CONCEPTUAL DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS PART II: CUBIC

PART II: CUBIC HIGHER ORDER CALCULUS. WOLFGANG BERTRAM. Abstract. Following the programme set CONCEPTUAL DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS. II. 5. 1.7. Homogeneity.





Course Code Course Title ECTS Credits MATH-191 Calculus II 8

Calculus II. 8. Department. Semester. Prerequisites. Computer Science. Fall Spring. MATH-190. Type of Course. Field. Language of Instruction. Required.



Wesleyan College

Calculus II. MAT 206 – Wesleyan College. Syllabus. Summer 2022 July 18 - August 19. Professor Contact Information. Professor: TBA.



Free Differential Calculus. II: The Isomorphism Problem of Groups

19 oct. 2007 Free Differential Calculus. II: The Isomorphism Problem of Groups. Ralph H. Fox. The Annals of Mathematics 2nd Ser.

CONCEPTUAL DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS

PART II: CUBIC HIGHER ORDER CALCULUS

WOLFGANG BERTRAM

Abstract.Following the programme set out in

Part Iof this work, we develop

aconceptual higher order differential calculus. The "local linear algebra" defined in Part I is generalized by "higher order local linear algebra". The underlying combinatorial object of such higher algebra is thenaturaln-dimensional hyper- cube, and so we qualify this calculus as "cubic". More precisely, we define two versions of conceptual cubic calculus: "full" and "symmetric cubic". The theory thus initiated sheds new light on several foundational issues.

Contents

1. Introduction1

2. The threefold way of higher order calculus7

3. The general pattern9

4. Symmetric cubic calculus16

5. Full cubic calculus21

Appendix A. Natural hypercubes28

Appendix B.n-fold categories and groupoids30

Appendix C. Then-fold pair groupoid33

Appendix D. Then-fold scaled action category35

Appendix E. Pullbacks in first order calculus36

References38

1.Introduction

1.1."Die Gesetze des Endlichen".In preceding work ([

Be15,Be08]), I quoted

the following phrase by G.W. Leibniz: "Die Gesetze des Endlichen geltenim Un- endlichen weiter" ("the rules of the finite continue to hold in the infinitesimal"), but I should admit that I really started to understand its meaning while working on the results to be presented here. When teaching differential calculus, we usually hasten to take the limit - "the infinitesimal" - and don"t ask ourselves what "the rules of the finite" are. Implicitly, we take for granted that these rules are kind of trivial and known by everybody. In the end, it may well appear that these "rules of the finite" look trivial; but they are certainly not known by everybody. They are trivial in the sensethat they "just"

2010Mathematics Subject Classification.14L10 14A20 16L99 18F15 22E65 51K10 58A03 .

Key words and phrases.differential calculus, double and n-fold groupoids and categories, cat rule, cubic calculus, scaleoid, synthetic differential geometry, 1

2WOLFGANG BERTRAM

deal with iterated directed products - but to say that, we need the subtle concept ofn-fold groupoid. I guess that such structures underly huge partsof mathematics. Some of the following is still tentative, andnotationis an important issue: I am not yet sure to have found the best one. For these and other reasons, the present version of this work will not be submitted for publication in a mathematical journal. I will start by introducing three different kinds of higher order calculus, then explain what their intrinsic, or conceptual, version is, and finally say some words about the relation between "the finite" and "the infinite". Let me stress once again that this is far from being a complete theory, but rather a first picture of the tip of an iceberg whose shape is still unknown, and the present work wouldhave reached its goal if the reader felt that something interesting and new is goingon here.

1.2.The threefold way of higher order calculus.Thefirst order conceptual

calculusdeveloped in [ Be15] (quoted as Part I) is based on a groupoid interpretation of thefirst order difference quotient map, orslope, of a mapf:U→W, (1.1)f[1](x,v,t) =f(x+tv)-f(x) t. Invertible scalarstrepresent "das Endliche" and non-invertible scalarstrepresent "das Unendliche" (witht= 0 as most singular value). Recall that, in a topological context (cf. Part I),fis calledof classC1if the slopef[1]extends to acontinuous map(still denoted byf[1]), for the valuet= 0 included. At higher order, there are three different ways to iterate this procedure (Section 2): •symmetric cubic calculus(closest to usual calculus), •simplicial calculus(closer to the spirit of algebraic geometry), •full cubic calculus(which includes both preceding approaches).

Briefly,full cubic calculus, as developed in [

BGN04], consists of iterating the proce-

dure in the "brutal way", that is, by looking at higher order slopesf[n]defined by f [2]:= (f[1])[1], and so on. These maps are very hard to understand, so let"s propose a "tamed" version of the iteration procedure: fix a scalartand consider the map (1.2)f[1] t: (x,v)?→f[1](x,v,t),

Iterating this, we definef[2]

t

1,t2:= (f[1]

t

1)[1]t2, and so on: at each step, we fix a scalar

t k, take the slope with this fixed value of scalar, and then look what happens when the multi-scalar (t1,...,tn) tends to zero (Section

2.2). In fact, this amounts

to consider a sub-structure of the "full"f[n], which turns out to contain already "most" of the information of the full map, and having the advantage that it is much easier understandable (Theorem

2.3). In particular, there is a natural action of the

symmetric groupSnpreserving the structure ("Schwarz" theorem"), whence the termsymmetriccubic calculus. However, for proving the general Taylor formula from [ BGN04], the symmetric cubic setting is not sufficient, and for this reason we have developed in [ Be13] asimplicial differential calculus. It should be possible and important (in particular, in order to relate the present work toapproaches used in algebraic geometry) to develop aconceptual and categorical formulation of simplicial calculus- however, to keep the present work in reasonable bounds, this is left for subsequent work.

CONCEPTUAL DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS. II 3

1.3.Conceptual version: the three symbolsGn,Gsyn,Gsin.I have chosen the

sans serif letterG, reminding the termgroupoid, combined withnstanding for the setn={1,...,n}, to denote certainn-fold groupoids, which are the conceptual objects corresponding to the three calculi. More precisely, •GnUis thefull cubicn-fold groupoidof the domainU,

•GsynUis thesymmetricn-fold groupoidofU,

•GsinUwill denote a simplicial (pre)groupoid version of the preceding. Before going ahead, I should reassure the reader who is not a specialist in category theory and who never before metn-fold groupoids and categories: I have been in the same situation, and so the present text is also designed to introduce a newcomer to these gadgets. In this respect, I hope that the presentationgiven here (Appen- dices AandB) may be useful:smalln-fold categoriesandgroupoidsare presented as "algebraic structures" in the usual sense, defined by sets, structure maps and identities, so a smalln-fold category is given by •a familiy of setsCα, one for eachvertexαof the natural hypercubeP(n), •a family of small categories, one for eachedge(β,α) of the hypercubeP(n), •such that for eachfaceof the hypercube these data define a small double category (as defined in Part I, appendix C). 1 Seen that way, smalln-fold categories are computable: forGsynUformulae are explicit and fairly simple (Theorem

4.3), whereas forGnUthey are far more com-

plicated - we make some effort to present them in algorithmic form, that could be programmed on a machine (Theorems

5.2,5.3,5.4).

Having said this, I hope the general reader is willing to accept that the iteration procedure, leading from first order to higher order conceptual calculus, is entirely "canonical", that is, following from general principles; once the concepts are clear, most proofs are "by straightforward induction": forn= 1, all three groupoids coincide with the groupoidU{1}defined in Part I, so, ifQis one of the symbols G,Gsy, thenQ1U=U{1}. Forn >1, to compute structure data ofQnU, we just have to apply a copy ofQ1to the data ofQn-1U. However, since the object set of G

1Uis a cartesian productU×K, we need to know howQbehaves with respect to

cartesian products and general pullbacks. At this stage, the difference between the three calculi comes in: the key notion to understand this is the one ofscaleoid.

1.4.Scaleoids, pullbacks and cartesian products.By "terminal object", we

mean the zero-subset{0}of the zeroK-module{0}; we just denote it by 0. The n-fold groupoidQn0 is called then-th order scaleoid. More precisely: •in symmetric calculus,Gsyn0≂=Kn, and since variablestkare kept constant at each iteration step, the groupoid structure here is the trivial one, •in full calculus, the top vertex ofGn0 isK2n-1, and then-fold groupoid structure is non-trivial and rather complicated.

1After having written this text, I found an essentially equivalent presentation, designed for

category theorists, in Section 2 of [ FP10]. See also [GM12], where a similar description is given forn-fold vector bundles, using a quite fancy terminology of "hops" and "runs", cf. Th. 4.7.

4WOLFGANG BERTRAM

To relate scaleoids with cartesian products, a basic property of our symbolsQnis thatthey are compatible with pullbacks(see Appendix

E): they satisfy the rule

(1.3)Qn(A×CB) =QnA×QnCGnB. The usual cartesian productA×Bis the pullback over a pointA×0B, whence (1.4)Qn(A×B) =QnA×Qn0GnB. Now, in symmetric calculus, the groupoidGsyn0 isKnwith trivial structure, so we can fix scalars, get ann-fold groupoidGsyntUfor fixedtand use the preceding relation in the form (1.5)Gsynt(A×B) =GsyntA×GsyntB, expressing thatGsyntis aproduct preserving functor, which is a well-established concept in differential geometry (see [

KMS93]). In particular, this relation implies

that the philosophy ofscalar extension, known from algebraic geometry and used in our preceding work [ Be08,BeS14,Be14], wholely applies in the present context. In full cubic calculus, sinceGn0 is highly non-trivial, computations cannot be untied so easily, and their description, though entirely explicit, is a bit tedious (Theorem

5.2). Certainly, the abstract algebraic structure of the full scaleoidGn0 deserves a

more profound study in its own right.

1.5.Iterated pair groupoids, and the rules of the finite.We consider the

n-fold groupoidGnUas ann-fold magnification of the "space"U. It is a kind ofn-th order version ofConnes" tangent groupoid(cf. Part I, Theorem 2.7), realizing an interpolation between then-th order tangent bundle and then-fold pair groupoid: recall that applying the natural iteration procedure to the pair groupoidM×Mover a setM, one gets then-fold pair groupoidPGnM(Appendix

C). Fort= (1,...,1),

and more generally fort= (t1,...,tn) such that eachtiis invertible, we have a natural isomorphism ofn-fold groupoids (1.6)GsyntU≂=PGnU. In full calculus, the situation is similar but more subtle (Theorem

3.8). Thus one

may say that "then-fold pair groupoid governs the rules of the finite". On the "infinitesimal side", fort= (0,...,0), we get theiterated tangent bundle (1.7)Gsyn(0,...,0)U=TnU which is not only ann-fold groupoid, but an "n-fold group bundle" since all target and source maps coincide fort= 0 (Theorem 4.7).

1.6.Symmetry.The general cubicn-fold groupoidGnUisnot edge-symmetric(in

contrast to those considered by Brown and Higgins [

BH81]). It is a non-trivial fact

thatGsynUisedge-symmetric (Theorem

4.3), and this symmetry can be interpreted

by saying that the "rule of the finite", stating that then-fold pair groupoid is edge- symmetric, continues to hold for all parameterst. By the way, this is the most natural proof ofSchwarz" theoremon the symmetry of second differentials, as given in topological differential calculus ([

BGN04,Be08]). In full calculus, the "rules of

the finite" are more complicated: there ought to be something replacing Schwarz" theorem - what it is, is not yet clear to me.

CONCEPTUAL DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS. II 5

1.7.Homogeneity.The next "rule of the finite" ishomogeneity under scalars. For

n= 1, it has been formulated conceptually as astructure of double categoryU {1} (Part I). By the general iteration procedure, in full cubic calculusthis leads to define asmall2n-fold categorythat we denote byG nU(the letterGis used although this is not a groupoid). Everything said so far aboutGnapplies here,mutatis mutandis, and the structure is, of course, even more complicated. However, since homogeneity makes no sense for a fixed scalart, this construction cannot be implemented into symmetric calculus, and we have to add homogeneity "by hand" as a property that can be respected (or not) by the morphisms ofGsynU.

1.8.Cn- andC∞-laws.Laws of classCnoverKare now defined in a canonical

way: they are morphisms ofk-fold groupoids fork= 0,...,n, each compatible with the preceding, and likewise forn=∞. These concepts can be defined with respect to each of the three symbolsG,Gsy,Gsi. ForK=R, or other topological base rings, and domainsUopen in topologicalK-modulesV, smooth maps give rise to such laws, in a unique way (Theorem

3.16). We also prove thatpolynomial laws

(in the sense of Roby, cf. Part I) give rise to laws of classC∞(Theorem

3.14). The

definition ofC∞-manifold lawsfollows the pattern given in Part I (see Section 3.8). Every law has a "finite part" which respects the "rules of the finite", since it is uniquely determined by its basic set-mapf(Theorem

3.15); however, the law need

not respect all "rules of the infinitesimal"; if it respects scalar actions, we call it homogeneous; if it respects symmetry, we call itsymmetric. According to "Leibniz principle", the laws induced by smooth maps in topological calculus do respect all rules. At a first glance, it might appear to be a drawback of our approach that such propertiesare not automaticfor abstract laws; however, in view of a deeper understanding, it rather opens the very interesting question of "classifying" such rules and of understanding "how many independent ones" of them exist, and it points the way towards calculi having different rules than the classical ones, such assupercalculus.

1.9.Towards geometry: the neighbor relation.In the present work, I concen-

trate on developing theformalism: then-fold groupoidGnMand 2n-fold small cate- goryG nMare canonical and chart-independent objects coming with any "smooth space"M, and they contain all information about its "smooth structure". Once the formal theory is developed, we may ask for its "geometric interpretation". Such geometric interpretation will be more "synthetic" than the usual, rather analytic, differential geometry, since we directly work with invariant and chart-independent structures. Indeed, we shall be able to use, in our framework, the language ofsyn- thetic differential geometry(SDG, see [

Ko06,Ko10,MR91]) - indeed, I believe that

the present approach yields a new and very interesting model of SDG. Such topics will be treated in subsequent work. However, to understand the present text, it may help the reader to have in mind some kind of "geometric picture", andtherefore I shall already here say some words on topics that will be taken up in later work. Let us call "primitive points" the elements of the point setMunderlying our smooth space, and think of then-fold groupoidsGnMas representing higher "stages" or "levels of definition" ofM, whence the proposition of terminology to callGnM

6WOLFGANG BERTRAM

then-th magnificationof the "spaceM" (for a most general theory, one will have to speak oflocaln-fold groupoids, cf. Part I, but this does not chage much in the following). More precisely, a pointahas "stage" or "levelk" if it belongs to a vertex setGα;nMfor a vertexα? P(n) of order|α|=k; so the primitive points are of stage 0. Every pointa?GnMhas ascale, which is its imaget=tain the scaleoidGn0 under the canonical morphismGnM→Gn0. A pointais calledfinite if its scaletabelongs to the finite partGfin0 of the scaleoid, andinfinitesimalelse.

Thefirst order neighbor relation, which Kock in [

Ko10] considers "the main actor"

of his presentation of SDG, can be defined as follows: say that two pointsa,bof same levelkand belonging to a common vertex setGα;nMarefirst order neighbors, a≂1b, if there exists an edge (β,α) such thataandbhave same image under the source projection of the edge category defined by this edge:πβ,α;n

0(a) =πβ,α;n

0(b). This relation is symmetric and reflexive, but not transitive since there areksuch edge projections! In symmetric calculus, neighbors have the samescale; in full cubic calculus, the situation is more intricate since the "magnifcationprocedure" is not only applied to the space, but also to the scale itself. Similarly, thesecond neighbor relation,a≂2b, is defined by usingdouble source projectionscoming from faces with top vertexα, and so on. As in SDG, it follows immediately that a≂kb,b≂?cimpliesa≂k+?c. Whena,b,care infinitesimal (with scale essentially zero), then heuristic arguments show that these neighbor relations coincide indeed with those used by Kock in [

Ko06,Ko10]. The advantage, compared to SDG, is

that the same terminology, and all arguments, literally also apply forfinite scale - all "synthetic reasoning" applies in a perfectly rigourous way if we start on the "finite side", by formulating things carefully in a language using natural groupoid strucures, and then letting scales "tend to zero". To carry this out, on the finite side, we may think of "points of levelk" in different ways: with regard to points of higher level, they are just "points" (objects); but with respect to points of lower level, they rather are "arrows" or "segments", namely, the "pointa" is interpreted as the segment or arrow from its sourcex=π0(a) to its targety=π1(a). If targets and sources match, such segments can be composed: this operation is natural, and it is preseved by all smooth maps. If targets and sources don"t match, there is no natural composition; however, there are unnatural compositions: this is what connection theoryis about (subsequent work). The groupoid aspect of connection theory, going back to Charles Ehresmann ([

E65,KPRW07]), is strongly stressed in

SDG ([

Ko10]), but I have the impression that only with the present approach it really becomes clear why it is so natural: the very foundations of calculus rely on it. I believe that many other topics of local differential geometry willbe amenable, in a similar way, to a "synthetic" approach giving a link between "the finite" and "the infinitesimal". Notation.We use small sans serif letters to denote the following finite subsetsofN:

1={1},2={1,2},3={1,2,3},...,n={1,...,n}.

We let alson?={1?,...,n?}be a formal copy ofn, disjoint fromn, and n:=n?n?={1,1?,2,2?,...,n,n?}.

CONCEPTUAL DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS. II 7

The power set of a setAis denoted byP(A). In particular,P(n) is thenatural n-hypercube, andP( n) is the natural 2n-hypercube (AppendixA). The naturaln- hypercube is the index set forn-fold categories (Appendix

B). To simplify notation,

for elements of aK-moduleV, instead ofv∅,v{1},v{1,2},...we throughout write v

0,v1,v12,..., and likewise for elements ofK.

Acknowledgment.I gratefully acknowledge that I have a permanent position at a public university. I also acknowledge having received the advice thatlong range and novel work is not suitable for mathematical journals, and that oneshould better wait and collect material until it is presentable in monograph form - I shall follow this advice (and I just hope that the delay will not be longer than theusual length of a human life). Anyways, comments and suggestions are welcome,and I thank the reader in advance for letting me know.

2.The threefold way of higher order calculus

2.1.Full cubic calculus.Recall from Part I the definitions ofU[1], (U[1])×, and

f [1]. The "full" cubic calculus ([

BGN04]) is based on direct iteration of (1.1).

Definition 2.1(Full cubicCn).Under the assumptions oftopological differential calculus(i.e.,Ka topological base ring with dense unit group,V,WtopologicalK- modules,Uopen inV; cf. Part I), a mapf:U→Wis calledof classCnif it is C n-1and iff[n-1]isC1; so the mapf[n]:= (f[n-1])[1]exists and is continuous on its domain of definition U [n]= (U[n-1])[1]. Thefulln-th order difference quotient mapf[n]has a "cubic structure": it is a combination of values offat 2nevaluation points. We use "cubic notation": for n= 1, instead of (x,v,t), we write (v0,v1,t1), andf[2]= (f[1])[1]is given by f [2]?(v0,v1,t1),(v2,v12,t12),t2? 1 t2? f [1]?(v0,v1,t1) +t2(v2,v12,t12)?-f[1](v0,v1,t1)? f(v0+t2v2+ (t1+t2t12)(v1+t2v12))-f(v0+t2v2) t2(t1+t2t12)-f(v0+t1v1)-f(v0)t2t1(2.1)Forn >2, it is rather hard to give a "closed formula" forf[n].

2.2.Symmetric cubic calculus.Things are considerably simplified if, at each

step, one "derives" only in direction of the "space variables"v, and suppresses derivation in direction of the "time variables"t: Definition 2.2(SymmetricCn,sym).Under assumptions as above, for fixedt?K, letUt:={(v0,v1)?V2|v0?U,v0+tv1?U}and write, for aC1-mapf:U→W, f [1] t:Ut→W,(v0,v1)?→f[1](v0,v1,t). By induction, for fixedt= (t1,...,tn)?Kn, we put, whenever defined, f [n] t:=f[n] t

1,...,tn:= (f[n-1]

t

1,...,tn-1)[1]tn:U[n]

t:= (...(Ut1)t2...)tn→W,

8WOLFGANG BERTRAM

and we say thatfisCn,symif it isCn-1,sym, and if the mapf[n-1] (t1,...,tn-1)isC1(so that, in particular,f[n] tis defined and continuous).quotesdbs_dbs23.pdfusesText_29
[PDF] Stewart - Calculus - Early Transcedentals 6e - VNUA

[PDF] Calculus Made Easy - Djmcc

[PDF] Calculus book

[PDF] 2017-2018 Official Academic Calendar - Carnegie Mellon University

[PDF] Ordinul MEN nr 4794_31 aug 2017_admitere in inv liceal 2018

[PDF] Academic Calendar Spring 2018 - The University of Texas at Dallas

[PDF] Calendario escolar 2016-2017 (185 días) - gobmx

[PDF] 2018-2019 Calendario Escolar

[PDF] Calendario 2017 Días festivos 2017

[PDF] Images correspondant ? calendario con semanas 2017 filetype:pdf

[PDF] Calendario diciembre 2016

[PDF] Calendario enero 2018

[PDF] Calendario julio 2017

[PDF] Calendario septiembre 2017

[PDF] CALENDARIO DOMINGOS Y FESTIVOS DE APERTURA PARA 2017